The Principle of Indifference, Discrete, and Continuous Distributions and the 6 / not 6 die.












0














Bertrand's Paradox is an example that is cited to show that the Principle of Indifference doesn't work for continuous distributions. The dogma is that there are multiple ways to choose "uniform randomness" with continuous distributions and that the various ways aren't invariant in assigning probability. For example the random radius and the random angle methods yield different results.



The dogma also is that discrete distributions are well behaved and you can apply the Principle of Indifference without problem. But are the discrete and continuous cases so different?



Let's say I have a normal 6 sized die spotted 1 to 6. What is the probability that I get a 6?



I can of course write down all the numbers thrown so so I get $53261352315...$ and so on. Since there are six digits each digit gets 1/6 probability.



But I could also write $bar6bar6bar66bar6bar66bar6...$ Now there are just two possible states and each should get 1/2.



But common sense... Well wait! What if the die was marked with a $6$ on one face and $bar6$ on the other five? Who is to say that I shouldn't just look at the indication on the face of the die?



It just doesn't seem to me that the different between the discrete case and the continuous case is so "obviously obvious to the casual observer" anymore. In both cases if you don't use the "right" probability distributions for the real world system that you're trying to model then you get burned.



What am I missing?










share|cite|improve this question
























  • With the six-sided die, there is a natural physical interpretation of what uniform means. Perhaps less so for the question "will there be a sunrise tomorrow?" or for the chords in Bertrand's paradox
    – Henry
    Nov 26 at 19:47












  • What's the question?
    – Mike Hawk
    Nov 26 at 20:19










  • @MikeHawk - Ok, fair enough. I added question "What am I missing?" to the post.
    – MaxW
    Nov 26 at 20:35










  • @Henry - Yes, but "natural" was supposed to be unambiguous in the discrete case. So for my die with $6$ & $bar6$ it seems "natural" to just write down what I see. I have to analyze the problem more deeply to figure out that the probability is 1/6, which is exactly where Bertand's chord paradox gets you.
    – MaxW
    Nov 26 at 20:40












  • The natural interpretation @Henry had in mind is for the sides themselves to be equally likely to land face up. If they're not, what makes one side more likely? The fact you drew a $6$ on it?
    – J.G.
    Nov 26 at 23:09
















0














Bertrand's Paradox is an example that is cited to show that the Principle of Indifference doesn't work for continuous distributions. The dogma is that there are multiple ways to choose "uniform randomness" with continuous distributions and that the various ways aren't invariant in assigning probability. For example the random radius and the random angle methods yield different results.



The dogma also is that discrete distributions are well behaved and you can apply the Principle of Indifference without problem. But are the discrete and continuous cases so different?



Let's say I have a normal 6 sized die spotted 1 to 6. What is the probability that I get a 6?



I can of course write down all the numbers thrown so so I get $53261352315...$ and so on. Since there are six digits each digit gets 1/6 probability.



But I could also write $bar6bar6bar66bar6bar66bar6...$ Now there are just two possible states and each should get 1/2.



But common sense... Well wait! What if the die was marked with a $6$ on one face and $bar6$ on the other five? Who is to say that I shouldn't just look at the indication on the face of the die?



It just doesn't seem to me that the different between the discrete case and the continuous case is so "obviously obvious to the casual observer" anymore. In both cases if you don't use the "right" probability distributions for the real world system that you're trying to model then you get burned.



What am I missing?










share|cite|improve this question
























  • With the six-sided die, there is a natural physical interpretation of what uniform means. Perhaps less so for the question "will there be a sunrise tomorrow?" or for the chords in Bertrand's paradox
    – Henry
    Nov 26 at 19:47












  • What's the question?
    – Mike Hawk
    Nov 26 at 20:19










  • @MikeHawk - Ok, fair enough. I added question "What am I missing?" to the post.
    – MaxW
    Nov 26 at 20:35










  • @Henry - Yes, but "natural" was supposed to be unambiguous in the discrete case. So for my die with $6$ & $bar6$ it seems "natural" to just write down what I see. I have to analyze the problem more deeply to figure out that the probability is 1/6, which is exactly where Bertand's chord paradox gets you.
    – MaxW
    Nov 26 at 20:40












  • The natural interpretation @Henry had in mind is for the sides themselves to be equally likely to land face up. If they're not, what makes one side more likely? The fact you drew a $6$ on it?
    – J.G.
    Nov 26 at 23:09














0












0








0







Bertrand's Paradox is an example that is cited to show that the Principle of Indifference doesn't work for continuous distributions. The dogma is that there are multiple ways to choose "uniform randomness" with continuous distributions and that the various ways aren't invariant in assigning probability. For example the random radius and the random angle methods yield different results.



The dogma also is that discrete distributions are well behaved and you can apply the Principle of Indifference without problem. But are the discrete and continuous cases so different?



Let's say I have a normal 6 sized die spotted 1 to 6. What is the probability that I get a 6?



I can of course write down all the numbers thrown so so I get $53261352315...$ and so on. Since there are six digits each digit gets 1/6 probability.



But I could also write $bar6bar6bar66bar6bar66bar6...$ Now there are just two possible states and each should get 1/2.



But common sense... Well wait! What if the die was marked with a $6$ on one face and $bar6$ on the other five? Who is to say that I shouldn't just look at the indication on the face of the die?



It just doesn't seem to me that the different between the discrete case and the continuous case is so "obviously obvious to the casual observer" anymore. In both cases if you don't use the "right" probability distributions for the real world system that you're trying to model then you get burned.



What am I missing?










share|cite|improve this question















Bertrand's Paradox is an example that is cited to show that the Principle of Indifference doesn't work for continuous distributions. The dogma is that there are multiple ways to choose "uniform randomness" with continuous distributions and that the various ways aren't invariant in assigning probability. For example the random radius and the random angle methods yield different results.



The dogma also is that discrete distributions are well behaved and you can apply the Principle of Indifference without problem. But are the discrete and continuous cases so different?



Let's say I have a normal 6 sized die spotted 1 to 6. What is the probability that I get a 6?



I can of course write down all the numbers thrown so so I get $53261352315...$ and so on. Since there are six digits each digit gets 1/6 probability.



But I could also write $bar6bar6bar66bar6bar66bar6...$ Now there are just two possible states and each should get 1/2.



But common sense... Well wait! What if the die was marked with a $6$ on one face and $bar6$ on the other five? Who is to say that I shouldn't just look at the indication on the face of the die?



It just doesn't seem to me that the different between the discrete case and the continuous case is so "obviously obvious to the casual observer" anymore. In both cases if you don't use the "right" probability distributions for the real world system that you're trying to model then you get burned.



What am I missing?







probability






share|cite|improve this question















share|cite|improve this question













share|cite|improve this question




share|cite|improve this question








edited Nov 27 at 7:35

























asked Nov 26 at 19:40









MaxW

651411




651411












  • With the six-sided die, there is a natural physical interpretation of what uniform means. Perhaps less so for the question "will there be a sunrise tomorrow?" or for the chords in Bertrand's paradox
    – Henry
    Nov 26 at 19:47












  • What's the question?
    – Mike Hawk
    Nov 26 at 20:19










  • @MikeHawk - Ok, fair enough. I added question "What am I missing?" to the post.
    – MaxW
    Nov 26 at 20:35










  • @Henry - Yes, but "natural" was supposed to be unambiguous in the discrete case. So for my die with $6$ & $bar6$ it seems "natural" to just write down what I see. I have to analyze the problem more deeply to figure out that the probability is 1/6, which is exactly where Bertand's chord paradox gets you.
    – MaxW
    Nov 26 at 20:40












  • The natural interpretation @Henry had in mind is for the sides themselves to be equally likely to land face up. If they're not, what makes one side more likely? The fact you drew a $6$ on it?
    – J.G.
    Nov 26 at 23:09


















  • With the six-sided die, there is a natural physical interpretation of what uniform means. Perhaps less so for the question "will there be a sunrise tomorrow?" or for the chords in Bertrand's paradox
    – Henry
    Nov 26 at 19:47












  • What's the question?
    – Mike Hawk
    Nov 26 at 20:19










  • @MikeHawk - Ok, fair enough. I added question "What am I missing?" to the post.
    – MaxW
    Nov 26 at 20:35










  • @Henry - Yes, but "natural" was supposed to be unambiguous in the discrete case. So for my die with $6$ & $bar6$ it seems "natural" to just write down what I see. I have to analyze the problem more deeply to figure out that the probability is 1/6, which is exactly where Bertand's chord paradox gets you.
    – MaxW
    Nov 26 at 20:40












  • The natural interpretation @Henry had in mind is for the sides themselves to be equally likely to land face up. If they're not, what makes one side more likely? The fact you drew a $6$ on it?
    – J.G.
    Nov 26 at 23:09
















With the six-sided die, there is a natural physical interpretation of what uniform means. Perhaps less so for the question "will there be a sunrise tomorrow?" or for the chords in Bertrand's paradox
– Henry
Nov 26 at 19:47






With the six-sided die, there is a natural physical interpretation of what uniform means. Perhaps less so for the question "will there be a sunrise tomorrow?" or for the chords in Bertrand's paradox
– Henry
Nov 26 at 19:47














What's the question?
– Mike Hawk
Nov 26 at 20:19




What's the question?
– Mike Hawk
Nov 26 at 20:19












@MikeHawk - Ok, fair enough. I added question "What am I missing?" to the post.
– MaxW
Nov 26 at 20:35




@MikeHawk - Ok, fair enough. I added question "What am I missing?" to the post.
– MaxW
Nov 26 at 20:35












@Henry - Yes, but "natural" was supposed to be unambiguous in the discrete case. So for my die with $6$ & $bar6$ it seems "natural" to just write down what I see. I have to analyze the problem more deeply to figure out that the probability is 1/6, which is exactly where Bertand's chord paradox gets you.
– MaxW
Nov 26 at 20:40






@Henry - Yes, but "natural" was supposed to be unambiguous in the discrete case. So for my die with $6$ & $bar6$ it seems "natural" to just write down what I see. I have to analyze the problem more deeply to figure out that the probability is 1/6, which is exactly where Bertand's chord paradox gets you.
– MaxW
Nov 26 at 20:40














The natural interpretation @Henry had in mind is for the sides themselves to be equally likely to land face up. If they're not, what makes one side more likely? The fact you drew a $6$ on it?
– J.G.
Nov 26 at 23:09




The natural interpretation @Henry had in mind is for the sides themselves to be equally likely to land face up. If they're not, what makes one side more likely? The fact you drew a $6$ on it?
– J.G.
Nov 26 at 23:09















active

oldest

votes











Your Answer





StackExchange.ifUsing("editor", function () {
return StackExchange.using("mathjaxEditing", function () {
StackExchange.MarkdownEditor.creationCallbacks.add(function (editor, postfix) {
StackExchange.mathjaxEditing.prepareWmdForMathJax(editor, postfix, [["$", "$"], ["\\(","\\)"]]);
});
});
}, "mathjax-editing");

StackExchange.ready(function() {
var channelOptions = {
tags: "".split(" "),
id: "69"
};
initTagRenderer("".split(" "), "".split(" "), channelOptions);

StackExchange.using("externalEditor", function() {
// Have to fire editor after snippets, if snippets enabled
if (StackExchange.settings.snippets.snippetsEnabled) {
StackExchange.using("snippets", function() {
createEditor();
});
}
else {
createEditor();
}
});

function createEditor() {
StackExchange.prepareEditor({
heartbeatType: 'answer',
autoActivateHeartbeat: false,
convertImagesToLinks: true,
noModals: true,
showLowRepImageUploadWarning: true,
reputationToPostImages: 10,
bindNavPrevention: true,
postfix: "",
imageUploader: {
brandingHtml: "Powered by u003ca class="icon-imgur-white" href="https://imgur.com/"u003eu003c/au003e",
contentPolicyHtml: "User contributions licensed under u003ca href="https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-sa/3.0/"u003ecc by-sa 3.0 with attribution requiredu003c/au003e u003ca href="https://stackoverflow.com/legal/content-policy"u003e(content policy)u003c/au003e",
allowUrls: true
},
noCode: true, onDemand: true,
discardSelector: ".discard-answer"
,immediatelyShowMarkdownHelp:true
});


}
});














draft saved

draft discarded


















StackExchange.ready(
function () {
StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f3014808%2fthe-principle-of-indifference-discrete-and-continuous-distributions-and-the-6%23new-answer', 'question_page');
}
);

Post as a guest















Required, but never shown






























active

oldest

votes













active

oldest

votes









active

oldest

votes






active

oldest

votes
















draft saved

draft discarded




















































Thanks for contributing an answer to Mathematics Stack Exchange!


  • Please be sure to answer the question. Provide details and share your research!

But avoid



  • Asking for help, clarification, or responding to other answers.

  • Making statements based on opinion; back them up with references or personal experience.


Use MathJax to format equations. MathJax reference.


To learn more, see our tips on writing great answers.





Some of your past answers have not been well-received, and you're in danger of being blocked from answering.


Please pay close attention to the following guidance:


  • Please be sure to answer the question. Provide details and share your research!

But avoid



  • Asking for help, clarification, or responding to other answers.

  • Making statements based on opinion; back them up with references or personal experience.


To learn more, see our tips on writing great answers.




draft saved


draft discarded














StackExchange.ready(
function () {
StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f3014808%2fthe-principle-of-indifference-discrete-and-continuous-distributions-and-the-6%23new-answer', 'question_page');
}
);

Post as a guest















Required, but never shown





















































Required, but never shown














Required, but never shown












Required, but never shown







Required, but never shown

































Required, but never shown














Required, but never shown












Required, but never shown







Required, but never shown







Popular posts from this blog

Le Mesnil-Réaume

Ida-Boy-Ed-Garten

web3.py web3.isConnected() returns false always