Well ordering and maximal chains in power set












4












$begingroup$


Let $M$ be a set and "$le$" a well-ordering of $M$. For $x in M$ define:
$$ M_{le x} := { y in M vert y le x } $$
The map
$$ f : M to mathcal{P}(M) , x mapsto M_{le x}$$
is injective and has the following property:
$$ x le y Leftrightarrow f(x) subseteq f(y)$$
Furthermore the set ${ emptyset } cup f(M) cup {M}$ is a maximal chain in $mathcal{P}(M)$ (ordered by "$subseteq$").
My question is: Does every maximal chain in $mathcal{P}(M)$ derive this way? Is there a bijection between the well-orderings of $M$ and the maximal chains in its power set? I was not yet able to proof that.





I would be super glad if this was even provable without the axiom of choice.
This would give a short proof of the well-ordering theorem by Hausdorffs maximal principle. Also, if $(M,le)$ is a partial ordered set and $K$ is a maximal chain in $mathcal{P}(M)$, I think that $f^{-1}(({emptyset} cup f(M) cup {M} ) cap K)$ (where $f$ is now defined via the partial ordering "$le$") is a maximal chain in $M$. So this would give a short proof of the maximal principle via well-ordering theorem. What do you think? I hope there is no obvious mistake...





Edit: Well, there was an obvious mistake and as you pointed out, maximal chains in $mathcal{P}(M)$ really dont need to relate to well-orderings of $M$. My original goal was to characterize the statement "$M$ is well-ordable" to a statement like "the maximal principle applies to $M$", whatever this should mean. I know the proof about maximal elements/chains in the set of partial well-orderings (well-orderings on subsets of $M$) being equivalent to well-orderings of $M$ but this doesnt seem useful to construct a maximal chain in $M$ if $M$ is partial ordered.










share|cite|improve this question











$endgroup$












  • $begingroup$
    As for your claim at the end, why would $f^{-1}(f(M)cap K)$ be maximal? You can find counterexamples to that even when $M$ has just two elements (try it!).
    $endgroup$
    – Eric Wofsey
    Dec 22 '18 at 2:26










  • $begingroup$
    Sorry, I wanted to write "$f^{-1}(({ emptyset} cup f(M) cup {M}) cap K)$". It will be corrected in the post.
    $endgroup$
    – Lucina
    Dec 22 '18 at 2:33










  • $begingroup$
    If $M$ is a countably infinite set, then the chains of the sort you describe are countable chains, but there are also uncountable chains in $mathcal P(M)$. For instance, the set of lower Dedekind cuts is an uncountable chain in the power set of the rational numbers.
    $endgroup$
    – bof
    Dec 22 '18 at 2:41










  • $begingroup$
    @Lucina: That doesn't help. The point is that maximality of $K$ in no way guarantees that $f(M)cap K$ is large, since most elements of $f(M)$ could be incomparable to elements of $K$. If you don't see this, I recommend actually thinking through what could happen if $M$ has two elements.
    $endgroup$
    – Eric Wofsey
    Dec 22 '18 at 2:45






  • 1




    $begingroup$
    Are you possibly confusing "well-ordering" with "total ordering?" Because your construction can be done with any total order on $M,$ and any maximal chain on $P(M)$ is a total order on $M.$
    $endgroup$
    – Thomas Andrews
    Dec 22 '18 at 3:14
















4












$begingroup$


Let $M$ be a set and "$le$" a well-ordering of $M$. For $x in M$ define:
$$ M_{le x} := { y in M vert y le x } $$
The map
$$ f : M to mathcal{P}(M) , x mapsto M_{le x}$$
is injective and has the following property:
$$ x le y Leftrightarrow f(x) subseteq f(y)$$
Furthermore the set ${ emptyset } cup f(M) cup {M}$ is a maximal chain in $mathcal{P}(M)$ (ordered by "$subseteq$").
My question is: Does every maximal chain in $mathcal{P}(M)$ derive this way? Is there a bijection between the well-orderings of $M$ and the maximal chains in its power set? I was not yet able to proof that.





I would be super glad if this was even provable without the axiom of choice.
This would give a short proof of the well-ordering theorem by Hausdorffs maximal principle. Also, if $(M,le)$ is a partial ordered set and $K$ is a maximal chain in $mathcal{P}(M)$, I think that $f^{-1}(({emptyset} cup f(M) cup {M} ) cap K)$ (where $f$ is now defined via the partial ordering "$le$") is a maximal chain in $M$. So this would give a short proof of the maximal principle via well-ordering theorem. What do you think? I hope there is no obvious mistake...





Edit: Well, there was an obvious mistake and as you pointed out, maximal chains in $mathcal{P}(M)$ really dont need to relate to well-orderings of $M$. My original goal was to characterize the statement "$M$ is well-ordable" to a statement like "the maximal principle applies to $M$", whatever this should mean. I know the proof about maximal elements/chains in the set of partial well-orderings (well-orderings on subsets of $M$) being equivalent to well-orderings of $M$ but this doesnt seem useful to construct a maximal chain in $M$ if $M$ is partial ordered.










share|cite|improve this question











$endgroup$












  • $begingroup$
    As for your claim at the end, why would $f^{-1}(f(M)cap K)$ be maximal? You can find counterexamples to that even when $M$ has just two elements (try it!).
    $endgroup$
    – Eric Wofsey
    Dec 22 '18 at 2:26










  • $begingroup$
    Sorry, I wanted to write "$f^{-1}(({ emptyset} cup f(M) cup {M}) cap K)$". It will be corrected in the post.
    $endgroup$
    – Lucina
    Dec 22 '18 at 2:33










  • $begingroup$
    If $M$ is a countably infinite set, then the chains of the sort you describe are countable chains, but there are also uncountable chains in $mathcal P(M)$. For instance, the set of lower Dedekind cuts is an uncountable chain in the power set of the rational numbers.
    $endgroup$
    – bof
    Dec 22 '18 at 2:41










  • $begingroup$
    @Lucina: That doesn't help. The point is that maximality of $K$ in no way guarantees that $f(M)cap K$ is large, since most elements of $f(M)$ could be incomparable to elements of $K$. If you don't see this, I recommend actually thinking through what could happen if $M$ has two elements.
    $endgroup$
    – Eric Wofsey
    Dec 22 '18 at 2:45






  • 1




    $begingroup$
    Are you possibly confusing "well-ordering" with "total ordering?" Because your construction can be done with any total order on $M,$ and any maximal chain on $P(M)$ is a total order on $M.$
    $endgroup$
    – Thomas Andrews
    Dec 22 '18 at 3:14














4












4








4


1



$begingroup$


Let $M$ be a set and "$le$" a well-ordering of $M$. For $x in M$ define:
$$ M_{le x} := { y in M vert y le x } $$
The map
$$ f : M to mathcal{P}(M) , x mapsto M_{le x}$$
is injective and has the following property:
$$ x le y Leftrightarrow f(x) subseteq f(y)$$
Furthermore the set ${ emptyset } cup f(M) cup {M}$ is a maximal chain in $mathcal{P}(M)$ (ordered by "$subseteq$").
My question is: Does every maximal chain in $mathcal{P}(M)$ derive this way? Is there a bijection between the well-orderings of $M$ and the maximal chains in its power set? I was not yet able to proof that.





I would be super glad if this was even provable without the axiom of choice.
This would give a short proof of the well-ordering theorem by Hausdorffs maximal principle. Also, if $(M,le)$ is a partial ordered set and $K$ is a maximal chain in $mathcal{P}(M)$, I think that $f^{-1}(({emptyset} cup f(M) cup {M} ) cap K)$ (where $f$ is now defined via the partial ordering "$le$") is a maximal chain in $M$. So this would give a short proof of the maximal principle via well-ordering theorem. What do you think? I hope there is no obvious mistake...





Edit: Well, there was an obvious mistake and as you pointed out, maximal chains in $mathcal{P}(M)$ really dont need to relate to well-orderings of $M$. My original goal was to characterize the statement "$M$ is well-ordable" to a statement like "the maximal principle applies to $M$", whatever this should mean. I know the proof about maximal elements/chains in the set of partial well-orderings (well-orderings on subsets of $M$) being equivalent to well-orderings of $M$ but this doesnt seem useful to construct a maximal chain in $M$ if $M$ is partial ordered.










share|cite|improve this question











$endgroup$




Let $M$ be a set and "$le$" a well-ordering of $M$. For $x in M$ define:
$$ M_{le x} := { y in M vert y le x } $$
The map
$$ f : M to mathcal{P}(M) , x mapsto M_{le x}$$
is injective and has the following property:
$$ x le y Leftrightarrow f(x) subseteq f(y)$$
Furthermore the set ${ emptyset } cup f(M) cup {M}$ is a maximal chain in $mathcal{P}(M)$ (ordered by "$subseteq$").
My question is: Does every maximal chain in $mathcal{P}(M)$ derive this way? Is there a bijection between the well-orderings of $M$ and the maximal chains in its power set? I was not yet able to proof that.





I would be super glad if this was even provable without the axiom of choice.
This would give a short proof of the well-ordering theorem by Hausdorffs maximal principle. Also, if $(M,le)$ is a partial ordered set and $K$ is a maximal chain in $mathcal{P}(M)$, I think that $f^{-1}(({emptyset} cup f(M) cup {M} ) cap K)$ (where $f$ is now defined via the partial ordering "$le$") is a maximal chain in $M$. So this would give a short proof of the maximal principle via well-ordering theorem. What do you think? I hope there is no obvious mistake...





Edit: Well, there was an obvious mistake and as you pointed out, maximal chains in $mathcal{P}(M)$ really dont need to relate to well-orderings of $M$. My original goal was to characterize the statement "$M$ is well-ordable" to a statement like "the maximal principle applies to $M$", whatever this should mean. I know the proof about maximal elements/chains in the set of partial well-orderings (well-orderings on subsets of $M$) being equivalent to well-orderings of $M$ but this doesnt seem useful to construct a maximal chain in $M$ if $M$ is partial ordered.







order-theory well-orders






share|cite|improve this question















share|cite|improve this question













share|cite|improve this question




share|cite|improve this question








edited Dec 23 '18 at 8:17







Lucina

















asked Dec 22 '18 at 2:13









LucinaLucina

655




655












  • $begingroup$
    As for your claim at the end, why would $f^{-1}(f(M)cap K)$ be maximal? You can find counterexamples to that even when $M$ has just two elements (try it!).
    $endgroup$
    – Eric Wofsey
    Dec 22 '18 at 2:26










  • $begingroup$
    Sorry, I wanted to write "$f^{-1}(({ emptyset} cup f(M) cup {M}) cap K)$". It will be corrected in the post.
    $endgroup$
    – Lucina
    Dec 22 '18 at 2:33










  • $begingroup$
    If $M$ is a countably infinite set, then the chains of the sort you describe are countable chains, but there are also uncountable chains in $mathcal P(M)$. For instance, the set of lower Dedekind cuts is an uncountable chain in the power set of the rational numbers.
    $endgroup$
    – bof
    Dec 22 '18 at 2:41










  • $begingroup$
    @Lucina: That doesn't help. The point is that maximality of $K$ in no way guarantees that $f(M)cap K$ is large, since most elements of $f(M)$ could be incomparable to elements of $K$. If you don't see this, I recommend actually thinking through what could happen if $M$ has two elements.
    $endgroup$
    – Eric Wofsey
    Dec 22 '18 at 2:45






  • 1




    $begingroup$
    Are you possibly confusing "well-ordering" with "total ordering?" Because your construction can be done with any total order on $M,$ and any maximal chain on $P(M)$ is a total order on $M.$
    $endgroup$
    – Thomas Andrews
    Dec 22 '18 at 3:14


















  • $begingroup$
    As for your claim at the end, why would $f^{-1}(f(M)cap K)$ be maximal? You can find counterexamples to that even when $M$ has just two elements (try it!).
    $endgroup$
    – Eric Wofsey
    Dec 22 '18 at 2:26










  • $begingroup$
    Sorry, I wanted to write "$f^{-1}(({ emptyset} cup f(M) cup {M}) cap K)$". It will be corrected in the post.
    $endgroup$
    – Lucina
    Dec 22 '18 at 2:33










  • $begingroup$
    If $M$ is a countably infinite set, then the chains of the sort you describe are countable chains, but there are also uncountable chains in $mathcal P(M)$. For instance, the set of lower Dedekind cuts is an uncountable chain in the power set of the rational numbers.
    $endgroup$
    – bof
    Dec 22 '18 at 2:41










  • $begingroup$
    @Lucina: That doesn't help. The point is that maximality of $K$ in no way guarantees that $f(M)cap K$ is large, since most elements of $f(M)$ could be incomparable to elements of $K$. If you don't see this, I recommend actually thinking through what could happen if $M$ has two elements.
    $endgroup$
    – Eric Wofsey
    Dec 22 '18 at 2:45






  • 1




    $begingroup$
    Are you possibly confusing "well-ordering" with "total ordering?" Because your construction can be done with any total order on $M,$ and any maximal chain on $P(M)$ is a total order on $M.$
    $endgroup$
    – Thomas Andrews
    Dec 22 '18 at 3:14
















$begingroup$
As for your claim at the end, why would $f^{-1}(f(M)cap K)$ be maximal? You can find counterexamples to that even when $M$ has just two elements (try it!).
$endgroup$
– Eric Wofsey
Dec 22 '18 at 2:26




$begingroup$
As for your claim at the end, why would $f^{-1}(f(M)cap K)$ be maximal? You can find counterexamples to that even when $M$ has just two elements (try it!).
$endgroup$
– Eric Wofsey
Dec 22 '18 at 2:26












$begingroup$
Sorry, I wanted to write "$f^{-1}(({ emptyset} cup f(M) cup {M}) cap K)$". It will be corrected in the post.
$endgroup$
– Lucina
Dec 22 '18 at 2:33




$begingroup$
Sorry, I wanted to write "$f^{-1}(({ emptyset} cup f(M) cup {M}) cap K)$". It will be corrected in the post.
$endgroup$
– Lucina
Dec 22 '18 at 2:33












$begingroup$
If $M$ is a countably infinite set, then the chains of the sort you describe are countable chains, but there are also uncountable chains in $mathcal P(M)$. For instance, the set of lower Dedekind cuts is an uncountable chain in the power set of the rational numbers.
$endgroup$
– bof
Dec 22 '18 at 2:41




$begingroup$
If $M$ is a countably infinite set, then the chains of the sort you describe are countable chains, but there are also uncountable chains in $mathcal P(M)$. For instance, the set of lower Dedekind cuts is an uncountable chain in the power set of the rational numbers.
$endgroup$
– bof
Dec 22 '18 at 2:41












$begingroup$
@Lucina: That doesn't help. The point is that maximality of $K$ in no way guarantees that $f(M)cap K$ is large, since most elements of $f(M)$ could be incomparable to elements of $K$. If you don't see this, I recommend actually thinking through what could happen if $M$ has two elements.
$endgroup$
– Eric Wofsey
Dec 22 '18 at 2:45




$begingroup$
@Lucina: That doesn't help. The point is that maximality of $K$ in no way guarantees that $f(M)cap K$ is large, since most elements of $f(M)$ could be incomparable to elements of $K$. If you don't see this, I recommend actually thinking through what could happen if $M$ has two elements.
$endgroup$
– Eric Wofsey
Dec 22 '18 at 2:45




1




1




$begingroup$
Are you possibly confusing "well-ordering" with "total ordering?" Because your construction can be done with any total order on $M,$ and any maximal chain on $P(M)$ is a total order on $M.$
$endgroup$
– Thomas Andrews
Dec 22 '18 at 3:14




$begingroup$
Are you possibly confusing "well-ordering" with "total ordering?" Because your construction can be done with any total order on $M,$ and any maximal chain on $P(M)$ is a total order on $M.$
$endgroup$
– Thomas Andrews
Dec 22 '18 at 3:14










2 Answers
2






active

oldest

votes


















3












$begingroup$

No. Indeed, let $Asubsetmathcal{P}(M)$ be any chain that is not well-ordered (such a chain exists as long as $M$ is infinite; for instance you can just take an infinite descending sequence where you remove one element at a time). By Zorn's lemma, $A$ is contained in some maximal chain $B$ of $mathcal{P}(M)$, which is not well-ordered since it contains $A$. Since all the chains you describe are well-ordered, this $B$ cannot be of that form.






share|cite|improve this answer









$endgroup$





















    2












    $begingroup$

    Your construction works for any total order on $M,$ not just well-orderings.



    And given a maximal chain in $P(M),$ you get a total order on $M.$ These are in 1-1 correspondence.



    Start of Proof: Let $C$ be a maximal chain in $P(M).$ Then $emptyset, Min C,$ because the chain wouldn't be maximal if they weren't.



    If $x,yin M$ we say $xleq_C y$ if and only if $forall Sin C$, if $yin Simplies xin S.$



    To prove:



    (1) This is a partial order. Reflexivity and transitivity are easy. The only hard part is proving if $xleq y$ and $yleq x,$ you'd have $x=y.$ This is due to the maximality of $C.$



    (2) This is a total order.





    The ultimate reason for this is that any maximal chain in $P(M)$ is closed under arbitrary unions and intersections. So the union $U_x$ of the elements of $C$ which do not contain $x$ and the intersection $V_x$ of all elements of $C$ which do contain $x$ are both in $C$, and there are no elements of $C$ strictly between $U_x$ and $V_x.$



    For (1), this means that if $xleq y$ and $yleq x$ then $yin U_x$ and $ynotin V_x.$ But this means that $U_xcup{y}$ is strictly between $U_x$ and $V_x.$



    For (2), this means that for $x.yin M,$ either $U_xsubseteq U_y$ or $U_ysubseteq U_x$, since $U_x,U_yin C$ and $C$ is a chain. But $U_xsubseteq U_y$ means $xleq y$ so either $xleq_C y$ or $yleq_C x.$






    share|cite|improve this answer











    $endgroup$














      Your Answer





      StackExchange.ifUsing("editor", function () {
      return StackExchange.using("mathjaxEditing", function () {
      StackExchange.MarkdownEditor.creationCallbacks.add(function (editor, postfix) {
      StackExchange.mathjaxEditing.prepareWmdForMathJax(editor, postfix, [["$", "$"], ["\\(","\\)"]]);
      });
      });
      }, "mathjax-editing");

      StackExchange.ready(function() {
      var channelOptions = {
      tags: "".split(" "),
      id: "69"
      };
      initTagRenderer("".split(" "), "".split(" "), channelOptions);

      StackExchange.using("externalEditor", function() {
      // Have to fire editor after snippets, if snippets enabled
      if (StackExchange.settings.snippets.snippetsEnabled) {
      StackExchange.using("snippets", function() {
      createEditor();
      });
      }
      else {
      createEditor();
      }
      });

      function createEditor() {
      StackExchange.prepareEditor({
      heartbeatType: 'answer',
      autoActivateHeartbeat: false,
      convertImagesToLinks: true,
      noModals: true,
      showLowRepImageUploadWarning: true,
      reputationToPostImages: 10,
      bindNavPrevention: true,
      postfix: "",
      imageUploader: {
      brandingHtml: "Powered by u003ca class="icon-imgur-white" href="https://imgur.com/"u003eu003c/au003e",
      contentPolicyHtml: "User contributions licensed under u003ca href="https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-sa/3.0/"u003ecc by-sa 3.0 with attribution requiredu003c/au003e u003ca href="https://stackoverflow.com/legal/content-policy"u003e(content policy)u003c/au003e",
      allowUrls: true
      },
      noCode: true, onDemand: true,
      discardSelector: ".discard-answer"
      ,immediatelyShowMarkdownHelp:true
      });


      }
      });














      draft saved

      draft discarded


















      StackExchange.ready(
      function () {
      StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f3049065%2fwell-ordering-and-maximal-chains-in-power-set%23new-answer', 'question_page');
      }
      );

      Post as a guest















      Required, but never shown

























      2 Answers
      2






      active

      oldest

      votes








      2 Answers
      2






      active

      oldest

      votes









      active

      oldest

      votes






      active

      oldest

      votes









      3












      $begingroup$

      No. Indeed, let $Asubsetmathcal{P}(M)$ be any chain that is not well-ordered (such a chain exists as long as $M$ is infinite; for instance you can just take an infinite descending sequence where you remove one element at a time). By Zorn's lemma, $A$ is contained in some maximal chain $B$ of $mathcal{P}(M)$, which is not well-ordered since it contains $A$. Since all the chains you describe are well-ordered, this $B$ cannot be of that form.






      share|cite|improve this answer









      $endgroup$


















        3












        $begingroup$

        No. Indeed, let $Asubsetmathcal{P}(M)$ be any chain that is not well-ordered (such a chain exists as long as $M$ is infinite; for instance you can just take an infinite descending sequence where you remove one element at a time). By Zorn's lemma, $A$ is contained in some maximal chain $B$ of $mathcal{P}(M)$, which is not well-ordered since it contains $A$. Since all the chains you describe are well-ordered, this $B$ cannot be of that form.






        share|cite|improve this answer









        $endgroup$
















          3












          3








          3





          $begingroup$

          No. Indeed, let $Asubsetmathcal{P}(M)$ be any chain that is not well-ordered (such a chain exists as long as $M$ is infinite; for instance you can just take an infinite descending sequence where you remove one element at a time). By Zorn's lemma, $A$ is contained in some maximal chain $B$ of $mathcal{P}(M)$, which is not well-ordered since it contains $A$. Since all the chains you describe are well-ordered, this $B$ cannot be of that form.






          share|cite|improve this answer









          $endgroup$



          No. Indeed, let $Asubsetmathcal{P}(M)$ be any chain that is not well-ordered (such a chain exists as long as $M$ is infinite; for instance you can just take an infinite descending sequence where you remove one element at a time). By Zorn's lemma, $A$ is contained in some maximal chain $B$ of $mathcal{P}(M)$, which is not well-ordered since it contains $A$. Since all the chains you describe are well-ordered, this $B$ cannot be of that form.







          share|cite|improve this answer












          share|cite|improve this answer



          share|cite|improve this answer










          answered Dec 22 '18 at 2:21









          Eric WofseyEric Wofsey

          191k14216349




          191k14216349























              2












              $begingroup$

              Your construction works for any total order on $M,$ not just well-orderings.



              And given a maximal chain in $P(M),$ you get a total order on $M.$ These are in 1-1 correspondence.



              Start of Proof: Let $C$ be a maximal chain in $P(M).$ Then $emptyset, Min C,$ because the chain wouldn't be maximal if they weren't.



              If $x,yin M$ we say $xleq_C y$ if and only if $forall Sin C$, if $yin Simplies xin S.$



              To prove:



              (1) This is a partial order. Reflexivity and transitivity are easy. The only hard part is proving if $xleq y$ and $yleq x,$ you'd have $x=y.$ This is due to the maximality of $C.$



              (2) This is a total order.





              The ultimate reason for this is that any maximal chain in $P(M)$ is closed under arbitrary unions and intersections. So the union $U_x$ of the elements of $C$ which do not contain $x$ and the intersection $V_x$ of all elements of $C$ which do contain $x$ are both in $C$, and there are no elements of $C$ strictly between $U_x$ and $V_x.$



              For (1), this means that if $xleq y$ and $yleq x$ then $yin U_x$ and $ynotin V_x.$ But this means that $U_xcup{y}$ is strictly between $U_x$ and $V_x.$



              For (2), this means that for $x.yin M,$ either $U_xsubseteq U_y$ or $U_ysubseteq U_x$, since $U_x,U_yin C$ and $C$ is a chain. But $U_xsubseteq U_y$ means $xleq y$ so either $xleq_C y$ or $yleq_C x.$






              share|cite|improve this answer











              $endgroup$


















                2












                $begingroup$

                Your construction works for any total order on $M,$ not just well-orderings.



                And given a maximal chain in $P(M),$ you get a total order on $M.$ These are in 1-1 correspondence.



                Start of Proof: Let $C$ be a maximal chain in $P(M).$ Then $emptyset, Min C,$ because the chain wouldn't be maximal if they weren't.



                If $x,yin M$ we say $xleq_C y$ if and only if $forall Sin C$, if $yin Simplies xin S.$



                To prove:



                (1) This is a partial order. Reflexivity and transitivity are easy. The only hard part is proving if $xleq y$ and $yleq x,$ you'd have $x=y.$ This is due to the maximality of $C.$



                (2) This is a total order.





                The ultimate reason for this is that any maximal chain in $P(M)$ is closed under arbitrary unions and intersections. So the union $U_x$ of the elements of $C$ which do not contain $x$ and the intersection $V_x$ of all elements of $C$ which do contain $x$ are both in $C$, and there are no elements of $C$ strictly between $U_x$ and $V_x.$



                For (1), this means that if $xleq y$ and $yleq x$ then $yin U_x$ and $ynotin V_x.$ But this means that $U_xcup{y}$ is strictly between $U_x$ and $V_x.$



                For (2), this means that for $x.yin M,$ either $U_xsubseteq U_y$ or $U_ysubseteq U_x$, since $U_x,U_yin C$ and $C$ is a chain. But $U_xsubseteq U_y$ means $xleq y$ so either $xleq_C y$ or $yleq_C x.$






                share|cite|improve this answer











                $endgroup$
















                  2












                  2








                  2





                  $begingroup$

                  Your construction works for any total order on $M,$ not just well-orderings.



                  And given a maximal chain in $P(M),$ you get a total order on $M.$ These are in 1-1 correspondence.



                  Start of Proof: Let $C$ be a maximal chain in $P(M).$ Then $emptyset, Min C,$ because the chain wouldn't be maximal if they weren't.



                  If $x,yin M$ we say $xleq_C y$ if and only if $forall Sin C$, if $yin Simplies xin S.$



                  To prove:



                  (1) This is a partial order. Reflexivity and transitivity are easy. The only hard part is proving if $xleq y$ and $yleq x,$ you'd have $x=y.$ This is due to the maximality of $C.$



                  (2) This is a total order.





                  The ultimate reason for this is that any maximal chain in $P(M)$ is closed under arbitrary unions and intersections. So the union $U_x$ of the elements of $C$ which do not contain $x$ and the intersection $V_x$ of all elements of $C$ which do contain $x$ are both in $C$, and there are no elements of $C$ strictly between $U_x$ and $V_x.$



                  For (1), this means that if $xleq y$ and $yleq x$ then $yin U_x$ and $ynotin V_x.$ But this means that $U_xcup{y}$ is strictly between $U_x$ and $V_x.$



                  For (2), this means that for $x.yin M,$ either $U_xsubseteq U_y$ or $U_ysubseteq U_x$, since $U_x,U_yin C$ and $C$ is a chain. But $U_xsubseteq U_y$ means $xleq y$ so either $xleq_C y$ or $yleq_C x.$






                  share|cite|improve this answer











                  $endgroup$



                  Your construction works for any total order on $M,$ not just well-orderings.



                  And given a maximal chain in $P(M),$ you get a total order on $M.$ These are in 1-1 correspondence.



                  Start of Proof: Let $C$ be a maximal chain in $P(M).$ Then $emptyset, Min C,$ because the chain wouldn't be maximal if they weren't.



                  If $x,yin M$ we say $xleq_C y$ if and only if $forall Sin C$, if $yin Simplies xin S.$



                  To prove:



                  (1) This is a partial order. Reflexivity and transitivity are easy. The only hard part is proving if $xleq y$ and $yleq x,$ you'd have $x=y.$ This is due to the maximality of $C.$



                  (2) This is a total order.





                  The ultimate reason for this is that any maximal chain in $P(M)$ is closed under arbitrary unions and intersections. So the union $U_x$ of the elements of $C$ which do not contain $x$ and the intersection $V_x$ of all elements of $C$ which do contain $x$ are both in $C$, and there are no elements of $C$ strictly between $U_x$ and $V_x.$



                  For (1), this means that if $xleq y$ and $yleq x$ then $yin U_x$ and $ynotin V_x.$ But this means that $U_xcup{y}$ is strictly between $U_x$ and $V_x.$



                  For (2), this means that for $x.yin M,$ either $U_xsubseteq U_y$ or $U_ysubseteq U_x$, since $U_x,U_yin C$ and $C$ is a chain. But $U_xsubseteq U_y$ means $xleq y$ so either $xleq_C y$ or $yleq_C x.$







                  share|cite|improve this answer














                  share|cite|improve this answer



                  share|cite|improve this answer








                  edited Dec 22 '18 at 19:13

























                  answered Dec 22 '18 at 3:36









                  Thomas AndrewsThomas Andrews

                  130k12147298




                  130k12147298






























                      draft saved

                      draft discarded




















































                      Thanks for contributing an answer to Mathematics Stack Exchange!


                      • Please be sure to answer the question. Provide details and share your research!

                      But avoid



                      • Asking for help, clarification, or responding to other answers.

                      • Making statements based on opinion; back them up with references or personal experience.


                      Use MathJax to format equations. MathJax reference.


                      To learn more, see our tips on writing great answers.




                      draft saved


                      draft discarded














                      StackExchange.ready(
                      function () {
                      StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f3049065%2fwell-ordering-and-maximal-chains-in-power-set%23new-answer', 'question_page');
                      }
                      );

                      Post as a guest















                      Required, but never shown





















































                      Required, but never shown














                      Required, but never shown












                      Required, but never shown







                      Required, but never shown

































                      Required, but never shown














                      Required, but never shown












                      Required, but never shown







                      Required, but never shown







                      Popular posts from this blog

                      Bundesstraße 106

                      Verónica Boquete

                      Ida-Boy-Ed-Garten