How strong are weak choice principles?











up vote
1
down vote

favorite












For this purposes of this question, a weak choice principle $W$ is a statement for which the following three statements hold





  • $ZFC$ proves $W$


  • $W$ is independent of $ZF$


  • $ZF+W$ does not prove $C$


Some examples of (what I think are) weak choice principles would be




  • Dependent choice

  • Countable choice

  • There exists a non-measurable set of reals

  • Ultrafilter lemma

  • Ultrafilter lemma, but only for filters on countable sets

  • Boolean Prime Ideal theorem

  • The countable union of countable sets is countable

  • The direct product of countably many nonempty sets is nonempty

  • Every infinite set has a countably infinite subset

  • Every infinite set is Dedekind-infinite


Now I've been able to look up the relations between some of these. Ultrafilter and Boolean Prime Ideal are equivalent. Countable choice proves countable union of countable sets are countable. Others I've had trouble with. Can countable choice prove the ultrafilter lemma?



So what I'm looking for is a nice big list of how various weak choice principles relate to each other. (Or, if there isn't such a thing, we make one.)










share|cite|improve this question






















  • No, countable choice can’t prove the ultrafilter lemma. There is Herrlich’s textbook and also Howard and Rubin’s big book of facts.
    – spaceisdarkgreen
    Nov 16 at 18:24








  • 1




    This is a whole diagram worth of answer. Also what do you mean direct product?
    – Asaf Karagila
    Nov 16 at 18:56






  • 2




    You know that hundreds of pages were written on these kind of questions, right?
    – Asaf Karagila
    Nov 16 at 18:58















up vote
1
down vote

favorite












For this purposes of this question, a weak choice principle $W$ is a statement for which the following three statements hold





  • $ZFC$ proves $W$


  • $W$ is independent of $ZF$


  • $ZF+W$ does not prove $C$


Some examples of (what I think are) weak choice principles would be




  • Dependent choice

  • Countable choice

  • There exists a non-measurable set of reals

  • Ultrafilter lemma

  • Ultrafilter lemma, but only for filters on countable sets

  • Boolean Prime Ideal theorem

  • The countable union of countable sets is countable

  • The direct product of countably many nonempty sets is nonempty

  • Every infinite set has a countably infinite subset

  • Every infinite set is Dedekind-infinite


Now I've been able to look up the relations between some of these. Ultrafilter and Boolean Prime Ideal are equivalent. Countable choice proves countable union of countable sets are countable. Others I've had trouble with. Can countable choice prove the ultrafilter lemma?



So what I'm looking for is a nice big list of how various weak choice principles relate to each other. (Or, if there isn't such a thing, we make one.)










share|cite|improve this question






















  • No, countable choice can’t prove the ultrafilter lemma. There is Herrlich’s textbook and also Howard and Rubin’s big book of facts.
    – spaceisdarkgreen
    Nov 16 at 18:24








  • 1




    This is a whole diagram worth of answer. Also what do you mean direct product?
    – Asaf Karagila
    Nov 16 at 18:56






  • 2




    You know that hundreds of pages were written on these kind of questions, right?
    – Asaf Karagila
    Nov 16 at 18:58













up vote
1
down vote

favorite









up vote
1
down vote

favorite











For this purposes of this question, a weak choice principle $W$ is a statement for which the following three statements hold





  • $ZFC$ proves $W$


  • $W$ is independent of $ZF$


  • $ZF+W$ does not prove $C$


Some examples of (what I think are) weak choice principles would be




  • Dependent choice

  • Countable choice

  • There exists a non-measurable set of reals

  • Ultrafilter lemma

  • Ultrafilter lemma, but only for filters on countable sets

  • Boolean Prime Ideal theorem

  • The countable union of countable sets is countable

  • The direct product of countably many nonempty sets is nonempty

  • Every infinite set has a countably infinite subset

  • Every infinite set is Dedekind-infinite


Now I've been able to look up the relations between some of these. Ultrafilter and Boolean Prime Ideal are equivalent. Countable choice proves countable union of countable sets are countable. Others I've had trouble with. Can countable choice prove the ultrafilter lemma?



So what I'm looking for is a nice big list of how various weak choice principles relate to each other. (Or, if there isn't such a thing, we make one.)










share|cite|improve this question













For this purposes of this question, a weak choice principle $W$ is a statement for which the following three statements hold





  • $ZFC$ proves $W$


  • $W$ is independent of $ZF$


  • $ZF+W$ does not prove $C$


Some examples of (what I think are) weak choice principles would be




  • Dependent choice

  • Countable choice

  • There exists a non-measurable set of reals

  • Ultrafilter lemma

  • Ultrafilter lemma, but only for filters on countable sets

  • Boolean Prime Ideal theorem

  • The countable union of countable sets is countable

  • The direct product of countably many nonempty sets is nonempty

  • Every infinite set has a countably infinite subset

  • Every infinite set is Dedekind-infinite


Now I've been able to look up the relations between some of these. Ultrafilter and Boolean Prime Ideal are equivalent. Countable choice proves countable union of countable sets are countable. Others I've had trouble with. Can countable choice prove the ultrafilter lemma?



So what I'm looking for is a nice big list of how various weak choice principles relate to each other. (Or, if there isn't such a thing, we make one.)







set-theory axiom-of-choice






share|cite|improve this question













share|cite|improve this question











share|cite|improve this question




share|cite|improve this question










asked Nov 16 at 18:04









eyeballfrog

5,688528




5,688528












  • No, countable choice can’t prove the ultrafilter lemma. There is Herrlich’s textbook and also Howard and Rubin’s big book of facts.
    – spaceisdarkgreen
    Nov 16 at 18:24








  • 1




    This is a whole diagram worth of answer. Also what do you mean direct product?
    – Asaf Karagila
    Nov 16 at 18:56






  • 2




    You know that hundreds of pages were written on these kind of questions, right?
    – Asaf Karagila
    Nov 16 at 18:58


















  • No, countable choice can’t prove the ultrafilter lemma. There is Herrlich’s textbook and also Howard and Rubin’s big book of facts.
    – spaceisdarkgreen
    Nov 16 at 18:24








  • 1




    This is a whole diagram worth of answer. Also what do you mean direct product?
    – Asaf Karagila
    Nov 16 at 18:56






  • 2




    You know that hundreds of pages were written on these kind of questions, right?
    – Asaf Karagila
    Nov 16 at 18:58
















No, countable choice can’t prove the ultrafilter lemma. There is Herrlich’s textbook and also Howard and Rubin’s big book of facts.
– spaceisdarkgreen
Nov 16 at 18:24






No, countable choice can’t prove the ultrafilter lemma. There is Herrlich’s textbook and also Howard and Rubin’s big book of facts.
– spaceisdarkgreen
Nov 16 at 18:24






1




1




This is a whole diagram worth of answer. Also what do you mean direct product?
– Asaf Karagila
Nov 16 at 18:56




This is a whole diagram worth of answer. Also what do you mean direct product?
– Asaf Karagila
Nov 16 at 18:56




2




2




You know that hundreds of pages were written on these kind of questions, right?
– Asaf Karagila
Nov 16 at 18:58




You know that hundreds of pages were written on these kind of questions, right?
– Asaf Karagila
Nov 16 at 18:58










1 Answer
1






active

oldest

votes

















up vote
3
down vote













Let me number those principles you mention.




  1. Dependent choice

  2. Countable choice

  3. There exists a non-measurable set of reals

  4. Ultrafilter lemma

  5. Ultrafilter lemma, but only for filters on countable sets

  6. Boolean Prime Ideal theorem

  7. The countable union of countable sets is countable

  8. The direct product of countably many nonempty sets is nonempty

  9. Every infinite set has a countably infinite subset

  10. Every infinite set is Dedekind-infinite


Equivalents




  • (9) is equivalent to (10). The direction (9) to (10) is easy, and (10) to (9) follows by taking an injection $fcolon Xsetminus Xsetminus{x}$ for some $xin X$ and looking at $f^n(x)$ for $ninBbb N$.

  • (4) is equivalent to (6). The proof from BPI to UF is fairly straightforward by noting that $mathcal P(X)/cal F$ is a Boolean algebra and a prime filter is an ultrafilter extending $cal F$. In the other direction, the standard proofs go through additional equivalents like compactness theorems for first-order logic, or compactness theorems for product of finite discrete spaces.

  • (2) is equivalent to (8). This is really just the definition of a choice function.


Implications, all strict.




  • (1) implies (2). By looking at the relation of extending choice functions from finitely many members of the countable family.

  • (2) implies (9) and (7). Given an infinite $X$, choose from the family ${A_nmid ninBbb N}$ where $A_n$ is all the injective sequences of length $n$. Prove that the union of the chosen sequences is countable.

  • (4) implies (5). Trivial.

  • (5) implies (3). Not trivial. This follows from the 0-1 law, or Lebesgue density lemma. Looking at $2^omega$ as a copy of the Cantor space, an ultrafilter, if measurable, is either of full measure or null. But a free ultrafilter is neither.


Anything else is not provable.




  • (4) is consistent with the failure of (10). This is Cohen's first model.

  • (1) is consistent with the failure of (3). This is Solovay's model. It does assume the consistency of inaccessible cardinals, a fact Shelah had shown to be necessary.






share|cite|improve this answer























  • Looking up the terminology, what I called the direct product is the Cartesian product.
    – eyeballfrog
    Nov 16 at 21:30






  • 1




    Okay. So that is just countable choice.
    – Asaf Karagila
    Nov 16 at 21:31











Your Answer





StackExchange.ifUsing("editor", function () {
return StackExchange.using("mathjaxEditing", function () {
StackExchange.MarkdownEditor.creationCallbacks.add(function (editor, postfix) {
StackExchange.mathjaxEditing.prepareWmdForMathJax(editor, postfix, [["$", "$"], ["\\(","\\)"]]);
});
});
}, "mathjax-editing");

StackExchange.ready(function() {
var channelOptions = {
tags: "".split(" "),
id: "69"
};
initTagRenderer("".split(" "), "".split(" "), channelOptions);

StackExchange.using("externalEditor", function() {
// Have to fire editor after snippets, if snippets enabled
if (StackExchange.settings.snippets.snippetsEnabled) {
StackExchange.using("snippets", function() {
createEditor();
});
}
else {
createEditor();
}
});

function createEditor() {
StackExchange.prepareEditor({
heartbeatType: 'answer',
convertImagesToLinks: true,
noModals: true,
showLowRepImageUploadWarning: true,
reputationToPostImages: 10,
bindNavPrevention: true,
postfix: "",
imageUploader: {
brandingHtml: "Powered by u003ca class="icon-imgur-white" href="https://imgur.com/"u003eu003c/au003e",
contentPolicyHtml: "User contributions licensed under u003ca href="https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-sa/3.0/"u003ecc by-sa 3.0 with attribution requiredu003c/au003e u003ca href="https://stackoverflow.com/legal/content-policy"u003e(content policy)u003c/au003e",
allowUrls: true
},
noCode: true, onDemand: true,
discardSelector: ".discard-answer"
,immediatelyShowMarkdownHelp:true
});


}
});














 

draft saved


draft discarded


















StackExchange.ready(
function () {
StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f3001455%2fhow-strong-are-weak-choice-principles%23new-answer', 'question_page');
}
);

Post as a guest















Required, but never shown

























1 Answer
1






active

oldest

votes








1 Answer
1






active

oldest

votes









active

oldest

votes






active

oldest

votes








up vote
3
down vote













Let me number those principles you mention.




  1. Dependent choice

  2. Countable choice

  3. There exists a non-measurable set of reals

  4. Ultrafilter lemma

  5. Ultrafilter lemma, but only for filters on countable sets

  6. Boolean Prime Ideal theorem

  7. The countable union of countable sets is countable

  8. The direct product of countably many nonempty sets is nonempty

  9. Every infinite set has a countably infinite subset

  10. Every infinite set is Dedekind-infinite


Equivalents




  • (9) is equivalent to (10). The direction (9) to (10) is easy, and (10) to (9) follows by taking an injection $fcolon Xsetminus Xsetminus{x}$ for some $xin X$ and looking at $f^n(x)$ for $ninBbb N$.

  • (4) is equivalent to (6). The proof from BPI to UF is fairly straightforward by noting that $mathcal P(X)/cal F$ is a Boolean algebra and a prime filter is an ultrafilter extending $cal F$. In the other direction, the standard proofs go through additional equivalents like compactness theorems for first-order logic, or compactness theorems for product of finite discrete spaces.

  • (2) is equivalent to (8). This is really just the definition of a choice function.


Implications, all strict.




  • (1) implies (2). By looking at the relation of extending choice functions from finitely many members of the countable family.

  • (2) implies (9) and (7). Given an infinite $X$, choose from the family ${A_nmid ninBbb N}$ where $A_n$ is all the injective sequences of length $n$. Prove that the union of the chosen sequences is countable.

  • (4) implies (5). Trivial.

  • (5) implies (3). Not trivial. This follows from the 0-1 law, or Lebesgue density lemma. Looking at $2^omega$ as a copy of the Cantor space, an ultrafilter, if measurable, is either of full measure or null. But a free ultrafilter is neither.


Anything else is not provable.




  • (4) is consistent with the failure of (10). This is Cohen's first model.

  • (1) is consistent with the failure of (3). This is Solovay's model. It does assume the consistency of inaccessible cardinals, a fact Shelah had shown to be necessary.






share|cite|improve this answer























  • Looking up the terminology, what I called the direct product is the Cartesian product.
    – eyeballfrog
    Nov 16 at 21:30






  • 1




    Okay. So that is just countable choice.
    – Asaf Karagila
    Nov 16 at 21:31















up vote
3
down vote













Let me number those principles you mention.




  1. Dependent choice

  2. Countable choice

  3. There exists a non-measurable set of reals

  4. Ultrafilter lemma

  5. Ultrafilter lemma, but only for filters on countable sets

  6. Boolean Prime Ideal theorem

  7. The countable union of countable sets is countable

  8. The direct product of countably many nonempty sets is nonempty

  9. Every infinite set has a countably infinite subset

  10. Every infinite set is Dedekind-infinite


Equivalents




  • (9) is equivalent to (10). The direction (9) to (10) is easy, and (10) to (9) follows by taking an injection $fcolon Xsetminus Xsetminus{x}$ for some $xin X$ and looking at $f^n(x)$ for $ninBbb N$.

  • (4) is equivalent to (6). The proof from BPI to UF is fairly straightforward by noting that $mathcal P(X)/cal F$ is a Boolean algebra and a prime filter is an ultrafilter extending $cal F$. In the other direction, the standard proofs go through additional equivalents like compactness theorems for first-order logic, or compactness theorems for product of finite discrete spaces.

  • (2) is equivalent to (8). This is really just the definition of a choice function.


Implications, all strict.




  • (1) implies (2). By looking at the relation of extending choice functions from finitely many members of the countable family.

  • (2) implies (9) and (7). Given an infinite $X$, choose from the family ${A_nmid ninBbb N}$ where $A_n$ is all the injective sequences of length $n$. Prove that the union of the chosen sequences is countable.

  • (4) implies (5). Trivial.

  • (5) implies (3). Not trivial. This follows from the 0-1 law, or Lebesgue density lemma. Looking at $2^omega$ as a copy of the Cantor space, an ultrafilter, if measurable, is either of full measure or null. But a free ultrafilter is neither.


Anything else is not provable.




  • (4) is consistent with the failure of (10). This is Cohen's first model.

  • (1) is consistent with the failure of (3). This is Solovay's model. It does assume the consistency of inaccessible cardinals, a fact Shelah had shown to be necessary.






share|cite|improve this answer























  • Looking up the terminology, what I called the direct product is the Cartesian product.
    – eyeballfrog
    Nov 16 at 21:30






  • 1




    Okay. So that is just countable choice.
    – Asaf Karagila
    Nov 16 at 21:31













up vote
3
down vote










up vote
3
down vote









Let me number those principles you mention.




  1. Dependent choice

  2. Countable choice

  3. There exists a non-measurable set of reals

  4. Ultrafilter lemma

  5. Ultrafilter lemma, but only for filters on countable sets

  6. Boolean Prime Ideal theorem

  7. The countable union of countable sets is countable

  8. The direct product of countably many nonempty sets is nonempty

  9. Every infinite set has a countably infinite subset

  10. Every infinite set is Dedekind-infinite


Equivalents




  • (9) is equivalent to (10). The direction (9) to (10) is easy, and (10) to (9) follows by taking an injection $fcolon Xsetminus Xsetminus{x}$ for some $xin X$ and looking at $f^n(x)$ for $ninBbb N$.

  • (4) is equivalent to (6). The proof from BPI to UF is fairly straightforward by noting that $mathcal P(X)/cal F$ is a Boolean algebra and a prime filter is an ultrafilter extending $cal F$. In the other direction, the standard proofs go through additional equivalents like compactness theorems for first-order logic, or compactness theorems for product of finite discrete spaces.

  • (2) is equivalent to (8). This is really just the definition of a choice function.


Implications, all strict.




  • (1) implies (2). By looking at the relation of extending choice functions from finitely many members of the countable family.

  • (2) implies (9) and (7). Given an infinite $X$, choose from the family ${A_nmid ninBbb N}$ where $A_n$ is all the injective sequences of length $n$. Prove that the union of the chosen sequences is countable.

  • (4) implies (5). Trivial.

  • (5) implies (3). Not trivial. This follows from the 0-1 law, or Lebesgue density lemma. Looking at $2^omega$ as a copy of the Cantor space, an ultrafilter, if measurable, is either of full measure or null. But a free ultrafilter is neither.


Anything else is not provable.




  • (4) is consistent with the failure of (10). This is Cohen's first model.

  • (1) is consistent with the failure of (3). This is Solovay's model. It does assume the consistency of inaccessible cardinals, a fact Shelah had shown to be necessary.






share|cite|improve this answer














Let me number those principles you mention.




  1. Dependent choice

  2. Countable choice

  3. There exists a non-measurable set of reals

  4. Ultrafilter lemma

  5. Ultrafilter lemma, but only for filters on countable sets

  6. Boolean Prime Ideal theorem

  7. The countable union of countable sets is countable

  8. The direct product of countably many nonempty sets is nonempty

  9. Every infinite set has a countably infinite subset

  10. Every infinite set is Dedekind-infinite


Equivalents




  • (9) is equivalent to (10). The direction (9) to (10) is easy, and (10) to (9) follows by taking an injection $fcolon Xsetminus Xsetminus{x}$ for some $xin X$ and looking at $f^n(x)$ for $ninBbb N$.

  • (4) is equivalent to (6). The proof from BPI to UF is fairly straightforward by noting that $mathcal P(X)/cal F$ is a Boolean algebra and a prime filter is an ultrafilter extending $cal F$. In the other direction, the standard proofs go through additional equivalents like compactness theorems for first-order logic, or compactness theorems for product of finite discrete spaces.

  • (2) is equivalent to (8). This is really just the definition of a choice function.


Implications, all strict.




  • (1) implies (2). By looking at the relation of extending choice functions from finitely many members of the countable family.

  • (2) implies (9) and (7). Given an infinite $X$, choose from the family ${A_nmid ninBbb N}$ where $A_n$ is all the injective sequences of length $n$. Prove that the union of the chosen sequences is countable.

  • (4) implies (5). Trivial.

  • (5) implies (3). Not trivial. This follows from the 0-1 law, or Lebesgue density lemma. Looking at $2^omega$ as a copy of the Cantor space, an ultrafilter, if measurable, is either of full measure or null. But a free ultrafilter is neither.


Anything else is not provable.




  • (4) is consistent with the failure of (10). This is Cohen's first model.

  • (1) is consistent with the failure of (3). This is Solovay's model. It does assume the consistency of inaccessible cardinals, a fact Shelah had shown to be necessary.







share|cite|improve this answer














share|cite|improve this answer



share|cite|improve this answer








edited Nov 17 at 0:42

























answered Nov 16 at 19:47









Asaf Karagila

299k32420750




299k32420750












  • Looking up the terminology, what I called the direct product is the Cartesian product.
    – eyeballfrog
    Nov 16 at 21:30






  • 1




    Okay. So that is just countable choice.
    – Asaf Karagila
    Nov 16 at 21:31


















  • Looking up the terminology, what I called the direct product is the Cartesian product.
    – eyeballfrog
    Nov 16 at 21:30






  • 1




    Okay. So that is just countable choice.
    – Asaf Karagila
    Nov 16 at 21:31
















Looking up the terminology, what I called the direct product is the Cartesian product.
– eyeballfrog
Nov 16 at 21:30




Looking up the terminology, what I called the direct product is the Cartesian product.
– eyeballfrog
Nov 16 at 21:30




1




1




Okay. So that is just countable choice.
– Asaf Karagila
Nov 16 at 21:31




Okay. So that is just countable choice.
– Asaf Karagila
Nov 16 at 21:31


















 

draft saved


draft discarded



















































 


draft saved


draft discarded














StackExchange.ready(
function () {
StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f3001455%2fhow-strong-are-weak-choice-principles%23new-answer', 'question_page');
}
);

Post as a guest















Required, but never shown





















































Required, but never shown














Required, but never shown












Required, but never shown







Required, but never shown

































Required, but never shown














Required, but never shown












Required, but never shown







Required, but never shown







Popular posts from this blog

Bundesstraße 106

Verónica Boquete

Ida-Boy-Ed-Garten